19.9.13

Sperry, the Split-Brain and the Perception of Consciousness

In a notebook Roger Walcott Sperry kept during the first semester of a university unit on psychology, he wrote: “Where does behaviour come from? What is the purpose of consciousness?” His work with split-brain patients did not answer either question, but it subsequently affected the way people thought about consciousness.

The corpus callosum is a dense fibrous bridge that connects the two hemispheres in the brain. Originally its purpose was not understood. One scientist remarked in the first half of the twentieth century that it might just be there to keep the two hemispheres from falling in on each other. Sperry clearly did not take this view, and the function of the “bridge” began to fascinate him.
In 1940 researchers first noticed the spread of epileptic (electrical) discharge, the cause of epileptic fits, from one brain hemisphere to the other in monkeys; they believed this occurred through the corpus callosum (Gazzangia, 2005). It was in this same year that William van Wagenen and R. Herren performed the first corpus callosotomies – essentially, the bisection of the brain into two separate hemispheres – to prevent epileptic fits in human patients (Matthews et al, 2008). By severing the corpus callosum, the epileptic discharges could not cross to the other hemisphere, thus preventing seizures the human patients had been suffering from. It appeared an operable cure for severe epilepsy had been found.
In 1944 A. J. Akelaitis began to study the first human split-brain patients to see if “there were any cognitive or behavioural effects as a result of the surgery” (Gazzangia, 2005). It became apparent very quickly that there were no disruptions of general intellect, nor was there impact on personality or temperament as a result of the procedure (Sperry, 1966b).
About ten years later, Sperry and his colleagues began to research split-brain rats, cats and monkeys; these early animal studies helped develop a set of more “sophisticated techniques to directly assess the function of each hemisphere independently” (ibid).
The ability to assess each hemisphere separately showed that the distinct sections of the brain solved problems differently. At the August 1968 meeting of the National Academy of Sciences, Jerry Levy-Agresti and Sperry presented that
the mute, minor hemisphere is specialised for Gestalt perception, being primarily synthesist in dealing with information input. The speaking, major hemisphere, in contrast, seems to operate in a more logical, analytic computer-like function. Its language is inadequate for the rapid complex syntheses achieved by the minor hemisphere. (Levy-Agresti & Sperry, 1968)
It was beginning to appear as if there were two minds within a single brain, theoretically meaning everyone had two consciousnesses.
In one experiment with a split-brain patient, a pornographic image was shown to the patient’s left eye. The left side of their face began to blush. When asked why they were blushing they didn’t know, they didn’t know they were looking at anything. This is because the left eye crosses to be connected with the right hand side of the brain. Language comes from the left side of the brain; this means when the patient is asked what they are looking at their brain doesn’t know the right hand side, their left eye, is looking at anything, as the connection between the two had been severed. This experiment showed that the two hemispheres are separately conscious at the same time. Sperry later wrote that
both the left and the right hemispheres may be conscious simultaneously in different, even in mutually conflicting, mental experiences that run along in parallel.
(Sperry, 1974)
It appeared as if consciousness could no longer be perceived as a single entity; it still remained, however,
a will-o’-the-wisp, something [science] cannot find, cannot demonstrate, measure or work with, and in most cases, something just the general nature of which it cannot even satisfactorily conceive or imagine. (ibid)
Consciousness was still “one of the most mysterious phenomena left in the whole of science” (ibid).
Following the “boom” period of split-brain research in the nineteen-sixties, more emphasis has been placed on the idea of two minds within each of us. Fredric Schifer’s book Of Two Minds argues that not only do we have two minds, but they also have their own distinct personality, making us two people in one body. To prove we have two minds that can work separately, Schiffer cites the case of a female split-brain patient. He writes:
A split brain patient was awakened by a hand slapping her across her face. Her alarm clock was going off, and she realised she had overslept and was going to be late for an appointment. The hand that had aroused her was her own left hand! While her left brain was asleep, he right brain [which controls the left hand] awoke and appreciated the predicament. (Schiffer, 1998)
This supports Sperry’s call that both hemispheres can operate independently and can be mutually conflicting in their processes.
We still cannot physically locate consciousness, nor can we measure it or recreate it artificially. The split-brain research, which widened the view of consciousness, shows that we, as yet, cannot define the parameters of it.
John Locke was the first to define consciousness in 1690; he said it was “the perception of what passes in a man’s own mind” (Locke, 1690). But the more science looks into the construction of the brain, the assumed location of the mind and consciousness, we have to wonder what the extent of the mind and consciousness is, something which may expand beyond what we can perceive to exist.
Sperry and his work with split-brain patients, while never answering the question he first asked himself at university in the early nineteen-thirties, has instead left us with more questions: “How far does the process of our consciousness proceed?”, “Are we more conscious than we can consciously be aware of?”, “Do we indeed possess two conscious and separate minds in the one brain?” and “Do we really consciously know who we are as individuals if we cannot know the extent of our consciousness?”
Click read more to reveal references
REFERENCES
Gazzangia, M S & Bogen, J E & Sperry, R W, 1962, Some functional effects of sectioning the cerebral commisures in man, National Academy of Sciences, vol. 48, no. 10, October 1962, pp. 1765 – 1769.
Gazzangia, M S, 2005, Forty-five years of split brain research and still going strong, Nature, vol. 6, August 2005, pp. 653 – 659.
Hamilton, C R & Hillyard, S A & Sperry, R W, 1968, Interhemispheric Comparison of Color in Split-brain Monkeys, Experimental Neurology, vol. 21, no. 4, August 1968, pp. 487 – 494.
Levy-Agresti, J & Sperry, R W, 1968, Differential Perceptual Capacities in Major and Minor Hemispheres, N.A.S. August Meeting: proceedings of the National Acadamies of Science, National Academies of Science, n.p., p 1151.
Locke, J, 1690, An essay concerning human[e] understanding, The Basset, London.
Matthews, M S et al, 2008, William P. van Wagenen and the first corpus callosotomies for epilepsy, J. Neurosurg, no. 108, March 2008, pp. 608 – 613.
McKean, K, 1985, Of Two Minds: Selling the Right Brain, Discover, April 1985, pp. 30 – 60.
Schiffer, F, 1998, Of Two Minds: the revolutionary science of dual-brain psychology, The Free Press, New York.
Sperry, R W, 1966a, Brain bisection and consciousness, in Eccles, J C (ed), Brain and Conscious Experience, Springer-Verlagen, New York.
Sperry, R W, 1966b, Some Head-Splitting Implications, The Voice, vol. 15, February 1966, pp. 11 – 16.
Sperry, R W, 1966c, Mind, Brain and Humanist Values, Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, vol. 32, no. 7, September 1966, pp 2 – 6.
Sperry, R W, 1968a, Mental unity following the surgical disconnection of the cerebral hemispheres, in The Harvey Lecture Series 6, Academic Press Inc, New York.
Sperry, R W, 1968b, Hemisphere deconnection and unity in conscious awareness, American Psychologist, vol. 23, no. 10, October 1968, pp. 723 – 733.
Sperry, R W, 1969, A modified concept of consciousness, Psychological Review, vol. 76, no. 6, pp. 532 – 536.
Sperry, R W, 1974, Changing concepts of mind, in Man and the Biological Revolution, University of Toronto Press, Toronto.
Sperry, R W, 1977, Bridging Science and Values: A unifying view of Mind and Brain, American Psychologist, April 1977, pp. 237 – 245.
Sperry, R W, 1979, Consciousness, freewill and personal identity, in D A Oakley & H C Plotkin (eds), Brain, Behaviour and Evolution, Methuen and Company, n.p.
Sperry, R W & Henniger, P, 1994, Consciousness and the Cognitive Revolution: A Trule Worldview Paradigm Shift, Journal of Humanistic Psychology, vol. 25, no. 2, September 1994, pp. 7 – 23.
Voneida, T J, c1994, Roger Wolcott Sperry, The National Academies Press, accessed 14 September 2013, <http://www.nap.edu/html/biomems/rsperry.html>.

































1 comment:

  1. Very informative and well researched. Well done.

    ReplyDelete